Defining and redefining monophyly: Haeckel, Hennig, Ashlock, Nelson and the proliferation of definitions

Similar documents
Geo 302D: Age of Dinosaurs LAB 4: Systematics Part 1

Cladistics (reading and making of cladograms)

The impact of the recognizing evolution on systematics

Modern Evolutionary Classification. Lesson Overview. Lesson Overview Modern Evolutionary Classification

Lecture 11 Wednesday, September 19, 2012

INQUIRY & INVESTIGATION

Introduction to phylogenetic trees and tree-thinking Copyright 2005, D. A. Baum (Free use for non-commercial educational pruposes)

Bio 1B Lecture Outline (please print and bring along) Fall, 2006

Introduction to Cladistic Analysis

Interpreting Evolutionary Trees Honors Integrated Science 4 Name Per.

17.2 Classification Based on Evolutionary Relationships Organization of all that speciation!

Systematics, Taxonomy and Conservation. Part I: Build a phylogenetic tree Part II: Apply a phylogenetic tree to a conservation problem

Title: Phylogenetic Methods and Vertebrate Phylogeny

Taxonomy and Pylogenetics

Species: Panthera pardus Genus: Panthera Family: Felidae Order: Carnivora Class: Mammalia Phylum: Chordata

History of Lineages. Chapter 11. Jamie Oaks 1. April 11, Kincaid Hall 524. c 2007 Boris Kulikov boris-kulikov.blogspot.

Are node-based and stem-based clades equivalent? Insights from graph theory

CLADISTICS Student Packet SUMMARY Phylogeny Phylogenetic trees/cladograms

HAWAIIAN BIOGEOGRAPHY EVOLUTION ON A HOT SPOT ARCHIPELAGO EDITED BY WARREN L. WAGNER AND V. A. FUNK SMITHSONIAN INSTITUTION PRESS

Understanding Evolutionary History: An Introduction to Tree Thinking

Phylogeny Reconstruction

What are taxonomy, classification, and systematics?

UNIT III A. Descent with Modification(Ch19) B. Phylogeny (Ch20) C. Evolution of Populations (Ch21) D. Origin of Species or Speciation (Ch22)

TOPIC CLADISTICS

LABORATORY EXERCISE 6: CLADISTICS I

PHYLOGENETIC TAXONOMY*

1 EEB 2245/2245W Spring 2014: exercises working with phylogenetic trees and characters

Ch 1.2 Determining How Species Are Related.notebook February 06, 2018

May 10, SWBAT analyze and evaluate the scientific evidence provided by the fossil record.

These small issues are easily addressed by small changes in wording, and should in no way delay publication of this first- rate paper.

LABORATORY EXERCISE 7: CLADISTICS I

Evolution and Biodiversity Laboratory Systematics and Taxonomy I. Taxonomy taxonomy taxa taxon taxonomist natural artificial systematics

Phylogenetics. Phylogenetic Trees. 1. Represent presumed patterns. 2. Analogous to family trees.

Modern taxonomy. Building family trees 10/10/2011. Knowing a lot about lots of creatures. Tom Hartman. Systematics includes: 1.

Comparing DNA Sequences Cladogram Practice

Do the traits of organisms provide evidence for evolution?

HENNIG'S PARASITOLOGICAL METHOD: A PROPOSED SOLUTION

Comparing DNA Sequence to Understand

Darwin and the Family Tree of Animals

Domesticated dogs descended from an ice age European wolf, study says

You have 254 Neanderthal variants.

Evolution as Fact. The figure below shows transitional fossils in the whale lineage.

Toward an Integrated System of Clade Names

Fig Phylogeny & Systematics

muscles (enhancing biting strength). Possible states: none, one, or two.

COMPARING DNA SEQUENCES TO UNDERSTAND EVOLUTIONARY RELATIONSHIPS WITH BLAST

LABORATORY #10 -- BIOL 111 Taxonomy, Phylogeny & Diversity

Phylogeny of genus Vipio latrielle (Hymenoptera: Braconidae) and the placement of Moneilemae group of Vipio species based on character weighting

Evolution of Birds. Summary:

6. The lifetime Darwinian fitness of one organism is greater than that of another organism if: A. it lives longer than the other B. it is able to outc

Natural Selection and the Evolution of Darwin s Finches. Activity Student Handout

Proceedings of the European Veterinary Conference Voorjaarsdagen

Required and Recommended Supporting Information for IUCN Red List Assessments

History of Evolutionary Thought. Part IV: Those Darned Pigeons! Natural Selection, I:

Warm-Up: Fill in the Blank

Testing Phylogenetic Hypotheses with Molecular Data 1

Fossilized remains of cat-sized flying reptile found in British Columbia

The Evolutionary Tree

Inferring Ancestor-Descendant Relationships in the Fossil Record

Management of bold wolves

1 EEB 2245/2245W Spring 2017: exercises working with phylogenetic trees and characters

Your web browser (Safari 7) is out of date. For more security, comfort and the best experience on this site: Update your browser Ignore

Evidence for Evolution by Natural Selection. Hunting for evolution clues Elementary, my dear, Darwin!

July 28, Dear Dr. Nouak,

Biodiversity and Distributions. Lecture 2: Biodiversity. The process of natural selection

Evolution. Evolution is change in organisms over time. Evolution does not have a goal; it is often shaped by natural selection (see below).

Let s Build a Cladogram!

RESOLVING THE TIBETAN MASTIFF DILEMMA

Mr. Bouchard Summer Assignment AP Biology. Name: Block: Score: / 20. Topic: Chemistry Review and Evolution Intro Packet Due: 9/4/18

Prof. Neil. J.L. Heideman

Persistent link to this record:

Cladistics, evolution and the fossils

COMPARING DNA SEQUENCES TO UNDERSTAND EVOLUTIONARY RELATIONSHIPS WITH BLAST

1 Describe the anatomy and function of the turtle shell. 2 Describe respiration in turtles. How does the shell affect respiration?

278 Metaphysics. Tibbles, the Cat. Chapter 34

Sample Questions: EXAMINATION I Form A Mammalogy -EEOB 625. Name Composite of previous Examinations

Red Eared Slider Secrets. Although Most Red-Eared Sliders Can Live Up to Years, Most WILL NOT Survive Two Years!

Chapter 13 Death by Decree

EDWARD RYDER of 40 Selkirk Road, Jimboomba, states:-

Global comparisons of beta diversity among mammals, birds, reptiles, and amphibians across spatial scales and taxonomic ranks

June 2009 (website); September 2009 (Update) consent, informed consent, owner consent, risk, prognosis, communication, documentation, treatment

Natural Sciences 360 Legacy of Life Lecture 3 Dr. Stuart S. Sumida. Phylogeny (and Its Rules) Biogeography

Nomination of Populations of Dingo (Canis lupus dingo) for Schedule 1 Part 2 of the Threatened Species Conservation Act, 1995

A Conglomeration of Stilts: An Artistic Investigation of Hybridity

Pedigrees: Understanding Retriever Pedigrees Part I

Evolution on Exhibit Hints for Teachers

Origin and Evolution of Birds. Read: Chapters 1-3 in Gill but limited review of systematics

CHAPTER XI. NEST-BUILDING, INCUBATION, AND MIGRATION.

INTRODUCTION TO ANIMAL AND VETERINARY SCIENCE CURRICULUM. Unit 1: Animals in Society/Global Perspective

Phylogeographic assessment of Acanthodactylus boskianus (Reptilia: Lacertidae) based on phylogenetic analysis of mitochondrial DNA.

Københavns Universitet. Companion animal ethics Sandøe, Peter; Corr, Sandra; Palmer, Clare. Published in: Luentokokoelma Publication date: 2013

The Application of Animal Welfare Ethics Student Activities

Animal Diversity III: Mollusca and Deuterostomes

Applicability of Earn Value Management in Sri Lankan Construction Projects

GEODIS 2.0 DOCUMENTATION

388 NOTES AND COMMENTS

Evolution by Natural Selection

What is the evidence for evolution?

The Divergence of the Marine Iguana: Amblyrhyncus cristatus. from its earlier land ancestor (what is now the Land Iguana). While both the land and

Ch. 17: Classification

Transcription:

CSIRO PUBLISHING Australian Systematic Botany, 2013, 26, 347 355 http://dx.doi.org/10.1071/sb13031 Review Defining and redefining monophyly: Haeckel, Hennig, Ashlock, Nelson and the proliferation of definitions Tegan A. Vanderlaan A,D, Malte C. Ebach A, David M. Williams B and John S. Wilkins C A School of Biological, Earth and Environmental Sciences, University of New South Wales, NSW 2052, Australia. B Department of Life Sciences, the Natural History Museum, Cromwell Road, London SW7 5BD, United Kingdom. C Department of Philosophy, University of Sydney, NSW 2006, Australia. D Corresponding author. Email: tegan_av@hotmail.com Abstract. The various existing definitions of monophyly have resulted in confusion within the systematics community. The divergence in terminology started with the work of Willi Hennig who attempted to introduce a precise definition of phylogenetic relationship in 1950, a term that he had synonymised with monophyly by 1953, thereby creating a new definition. In 1965, Hennig introduced paraphyly to distinguish his version of monophyly from groups based on symplesiomorphies or stem groups. In attempting to resolve the confusion, Ashlock synonymised Hennig s monophyly as holophyly, resulting in another new term. Ashlock, Mayr and others defended Haeckel s original use of monophyly, by including holophyly and paraphyly. The result was an unresolved 21-year debate on monophyly and its various uses. A review of the history of monophyly and the origins of its various definitions has resulted in two new terms to distinguish the different versions of monophyly currently in use: diamonophyly, which group definitions based a notion of ancestordescendant relationships, and synmonophyly, which groups definition based on kinship relationships. The terms reciprocal monophyly and oligophyly are discussed as being diamonophyletic. Additional keywords: diamonophyly, holophyly, oligophyly, paraphyly, synmonophyly. Received 15 July 2013, accepted 13 November 2013, published online 20 December 2013 Introduction Citius emergit veritas ex errore quam ex confusione. [Hennig 1950] The general confusion as to the interpretation of the concept phylogenetic relationship can be characterised as the dilemma of systematics. [Brundin 1966, p. 16] Throughout the late 19th and early 20th centuries, the term monophyly, a neologism coined by Haeckel (1866), was used in a very loose way, meaning that either all organisms originate from just a single stem form (Stamm-form) (Richards 2008; Rieppel 2011) or a single origin of the animal kingdom (Ashlock 1984). Biologists Ernst Mayr (1942), Robert Sidney Bigelow (1956) and George Gaylord Simpson (1961) redefined the term to be more specific, to include a species concept (Mayr and Simpson), and a time concept (Bigelow). German entomologist Willi Hennig took up these ideas in his 1966 revision of Hennig (1950), changing his original definition to include the species and time concepts of Mayr and Bigelow, while incorporating his original ideas on phylogeny. At the same time, Brundin (1966) had used Hennig s original (Hennig 1950) definition of monophyly to propose his own definition. Regardless, Mayr and Simpson, and in particular Peter Ashlock, found the now more widely read definitions of Journal compilation CSIRO 2013 Hennig (1950, 1966) to be far too restrictive. Rather, it was the exclusion of paraphyletic taxa from a monophyletic group sensu Hennig that began the modern debate on the meaning of monophyly (Hennig 1965). When Hennig defined monophyly as a concept separate from paraphyly, it invoked responses from Ashlock and likeminded evolutionary biologists. A debate ensued from the newly emerging cladists, followers of Hennig s theoretical work that he referred to as phylogenetic systematics, and the more traditional evolutionary biologists. The debates centred on the definition of monophyly touched on two important issues, but were not appreciated at the time. The first of these issues was whether the definition was based on a genealogical phylogenetic inference, and the second whether it was based on a concept about kinship, that is topological relationship. These issues have been the driving force behind the prolonged debate, which in recent times has devolved into the following three distinct positions: (1) those that consider monophyly to be a stem group (e.g. Ashlock 1971), which include aphyly (see Ebach and Williams 2010) and holophyly; (2) those that consider monophyly to include the most recent common ancestor and all of its descendants (e.g. Hennig 1966) and (3) those that consider monophyly to be topographical relations, namely when two taxa are more closely related to each other than they are to a third (e.g. Nelson 1994). www.publish.csiro.au/journals/asb

348 Australian Systematic Botany T. A. Vanderlaan et al. Hennig and Brundin: a new definition of monophyly Hennig (1965, 1966), as well as the theoretical parts of Brundin (1966), are derived from Hennig (1950) (see also Schmitt 2013 for a summary on the Brundin Hennig correspondence). These publications discussed the merits of phylogenetic systematics, such as the use of synapomorphy, to make statements about monophyly. The evolution of Hennig s monophyly The first definition Hennig gave of monophyly was as follows:...monophyletic groups of species and these are all groups of higher rank are referred to as those that ultimately can be traced back to a common ancestral species... must be added that a monophyletic group must not only include species that are derived from a common ancestral species, rather that they must include in addition, all the species that come from this ancestral species. [translated from Hennig 1950, pp. 307 308] In his following publications, Hennig s definitions were consistent with that given in 1950, although the wording changed considerably. Hennig defined a monophyletic group as Monophyletic groups are small or large species-groups whose member species can be considered to be more closely related to one another than to species which stand outside these groups. [Hennig 1965, p. 98] He later went on to write that The supposition that two or more species are more closely related to one another than to any other species, and that, together they form a monophyletic group, can only be confirmed by demonstrating their common possession of derivative characters ( synapomorphy ). When such characters have been demonstrated, then the supposition has been confirmed that they have been inherited from an ancestral species common only to the species showing these characters. [Hennig 1965, p. 104] A year later, the first definition was given as A monophyletic group is a group of species descended from a single ( stem ) species, and which includes all species descended from this stem species. Briefly, a monophyletic group comprises all descendants of a group of individuals that at their time belonged to a (potential) reproductive community, i.e. to a single species. [Hennig 1966, p. 73] Hennig (1966) claimed to have developed this definition from two authors, namely, Mayr (1942) and Bigelow (1956). Mayr (1942) was attributed by Hennig as representing the commonly used definition of monophyly, as follows: The definition of Mayr (1942) probably represents a widely held view: we employ the term monophyletic as meaning descendants of a single interbreeding group of populations, in other words, descendants of a single species. [Hennig 1966, p. 72] This lacked the important dimension of time for Hennig, so he then added Bigelow s (1956) definition, and stated that Unless the time element is introduced, say, as follows: the members of a monophyletic group share a more recent common ancestry with one another than with any member of any other such group of equal categorical rank, the term monophyletic is meaningless. The time element is the very essence of monophyletic classification. [Hennig 1966, p. 145] Hennig s first definition appears to be extremely similar to that of Mayr, even though he claims Mayr s definition is incomplete. Although Hennig cited Bigelow as a source of a time aspect, this concept was extremely vague in Hennig (1966). So much so, it would be forgiven if a third party read both definitions and did not see a difference. The placement of Hennig s (1966) first definition was not consistent with the placement of Hennig s (1950) definition. Monophyly was first defined by Hennig (1966), and included the now widely used diagrams depicting monophyly v. paraphyly and polyphyly (Hennig 1966, fig. 45). Compare this to the definition of monophyly and polyphyly in Hennig (1950) and one can see it occurs much later in the book on page 307. Hennig s (1950) book did not incur the reaction from evolutionary taxonomists in regard to the definition of monophyly that his 1966 book (Hennig 1966) received. Mayr (1965) did criticise his use of a purely cladistic view, especially in regard to monophyly. After the Hennig s (1966) book was published, there was a much greater number of criticisms of his theories on phylogenetic systematics (Colless 1967; Bock 1968, 1973; Mayr 1969, 1974; Darlington 1970, 1972; Ashlock 1971, 1972, 1974, to name a few). Time and time again, authors such as Mayr, Bock and Ashlock took offence to Hennig s redefinition of monophyly. For example, Bock stated that...controversies have arisen over the past decade largely because of redefinition of long established terms such as monophyly by cladists. [Bock 1973, p. 383] As shown above, Hennig did not redefine monophyly in his 1966 book (Hennig 1966), but did so as far back as in his first book (Hennig 1950). One possible explanation is that his latter papers and his 1966 book (Hennig 1966) were much more widely available to audiences because they were written in English (Schmitt 2013). Although this was true to an extent, his 1950 book was cited by Borgmeier (1957), Mayr (1965), Sokal and Camin (1965), Sattler (1964) and Kiriakoff (1959), proving that it had been read before his 1966 book was published. Why then was his definition of monophyly not criticised as much as it was after his 1966 book was published? The placement of the definition of monophyly lends a clue; in his 1950 book (Hennig 1950) it was on page 307, whereas in his 1966 book (Hennig 1966) it was on page 73. The change between Hennig s books can be seen as a change in focus on concepts. It would appear monophyly was not as important to him as the concept of phylogenetic relationship, which is discussed throughout the beginning, middle and end of his 1950 book (with monophyly almost as an afterthought). The 1966 book, however, dramatically changed focus from phylogenetic relationships to monophyletic groups. It could

Defining and redefining Monophyly Australian Systematic Botany 349 be suggested that Hennig was now using the term monophyly as a replacement for phylogenetic relationships. The definition of monophyly in 1950 did not come under fire the way it did in 1966, and it may be that this sudden focus on monophyly, and its very rigid definition, was a source of concern for those who did not agree. Hennig s second definition and Brundin The second definition Hennig gave was Another definition is: a monophyletic group is a group of species in which every species is more closely related to every other species than to any species that is classified outside this group. [Hennig 1966, p. 73] This definition was connected to the idea of kinship, a concept Hennig disliked. He felt it was interchangeable with affinity, defined by Cain and Harrison (1958) on overall similarity. The second definition could in fact be attributed to Cain and Harrison, who stated the following: Whenever a taxonomist (or anyone else) says of three things that on their overall resemblance or general likeness or some such property, two of them are more closely related to each other than is either to a third, he is making a judgement of affinity of an extremely familiar sort. [Cain and Harrison 1958, p. 85; italics in original] Hennig preferred the word relationship to affinity, which he defined as A species x is more closely related to another species y than it is to a third species z if, and only if, it has at least one stem species in common with species y that is not also a stem species of z [Hennig 1966, p. 74]. This definition of relationship was created by Hennig to include the stem species, or a notion of genealogy, rather than overall similarity. It was derived from Zimmermann (1931), who stated that The relative age relationship of ancestors X 1 and X 2 is the only direct measure of phylogenetic relationship. [Zimmermann 1931, pp. 989 990] Genealogy was supported by Hennig over kinship (i.e. the concepts of age and ancestors over overall similarity). Hennig (1966) also stated that in all definitions of a monophyletic group (presumably he was referring to Mayr s, Bigelow s and his own, although he did not state this), it must include all species or individuals descended from the stem species, and that none of the derived species be allocated outside the group. The next definition was supplied by Brundin, and was as follows: The definition of a monophyletic group is a direct consequence of the definition of phylogenetic relationship: monophyletic is every group of the system fulfilling the demand that any species belonging to it is more closely related to any other species likewise belonging to the group than to any species which does not belong to it. [Brundin 1966, p. 17, original emphasis] And he went on to add that It is important to note not only that a monophyletic group may comprise species which are derivable from a common ancestral species, but, what is the more, that it must comprise all species derivable from that ancestral species. [Brundin 1966, p. 17] Brundin s definition included both of Hennig s (1966) definitions, by including both the kinship and genealogical concepts. Brundin also made the particular point that all species must be included in the group to be monophyletic, which was taken from Hennig (1953). Hennig was very clear about this (Hennig 1966, see above). It is interesting to note that at this point, Brundin did not include the stem species discussed in detail in Hennig s (1966) definition. Monophyly was defined by Hennig to support his overall theory that classification should be based on phylogenetic principles, not overall similarity (Richter and Meier 1994). The concept of time was important to Hennig, because it encompassed his ideas of phylogeny based on Zimmermann s definition. Brundin (1966), however, gave a definition of monophyly that was based on Hennig s (1953) original definitions. Monophyly was defined by Brundin on Hennig s principles, but was intended to be applied to biogeographical concepts (Brundin 1966). Several early publications on the use of phylogeny in systematics referred to both Hennig (1966) and Brundin (1966) as their source of theoretical work (Mayr 1969; Nelson 1969, 1972, 1973; Darlington 1970). It was the reading and understanding of these two authors that sparked the beginning of the debate over the definition of monophyly. The beginning of the debate: Ashlock v. Nelson US heteropterist, Peter D. Ashlock, was an early adopter of phylogenetic systematics, having been introduced to Hennig (1950) by fellow entomologist Pedro Wygodzinsky in 1961 (Slater and Polhemus 1990, p. 115). While learning Hennig s approach, Ashlock (1971) published a definition of monophyly that he felt would encompass both the traditional definition of monophyly and the newer definition of Hennig (1966). Ashlock did not find fault with Hennig s version of monophyly, rather he found it far too restrictive:...since it is more restricted in meaning than that generally held, it probably should be renamed. I proposed the word holophyly, a tribe of all, for the concept that Hennig calls monophyly. Holophyly and paraphyly, then, become two aspects of the more general concept, monophyly [Ashlock 1971, p. 65]. The exclusion of paraphyletic taxa went against Ashlock s views of traditional monophyletic groups. It was this exclusion of paraphyly from monophyly that led Ashlock (1971) to formally redefine monophyly, holophyly and paraphyly, as follows: A monophyletic group is one whose most recent common ancestor is cladistically a member of that group. A holophyletic group is a monophyletic group that contains all of the descendants of the most recent common ancestor of that group (monophyly of Hennig).

350 Australian Systematic Botany T. A. Vanderlaan et al. A paraphyletic group is a monophyletic group that does not contain all of the descendants of the most recent common ancestor of that group. [Ashlock 1971, pp. 68 69, original emphasis] Why would Ashlock wish to redefine monophyly? Ashlock s definition of monophyly deliberately included paraphyly. Given that many recognised groups, such as Reptilia, for example, were paraphyletic, Ashlock believed that they should be retained as monophyletic, despite Hennig s (1966) views. The redefinition preserved all names and recognised all definitions as useful to classification. Ashlock was considered an early proponent of the cladistic method, and his views, along with that of Wygodzinsky, resounded more with evolutionary biologists such as Mayr, particularly in the adoption of Hennig s monophyly in biological classification (Slater and Polhemus 1990). Then why is Ashlock seen as detrimental to the development of cladistics? Slater and Polhemus (1990, p. 116) believed Ashlock s defense of paraphyly lost him much of his standing in the coterie of the new cladists. Although this might be true for some debates (Nelson 1973), it does not necessary ring true for others (Ashlock 1971), as we will show below. Ashlock (1971) introduced a new term to distinguish one type of monophyly from another, thereby unwittingly reducing the ambiguity of the term monophyly. Interestingly, although Ashlock ascribed the term holophyly to Hennig s definition, he did not cite a source for the original term, stating that Systematists have long used the term monophyly and have felt sure they knew what was meant when they used it [Ashlock 1971, p. 63]. Although the ambiguity of terms is presently seen as an issue, it was not as problematic as the defence of paraphyly and paraphyletic groups. Nelson (1971) responded to Ashlock s(1971) paper with his own definitions. But, these were definitions for paraphyly and polyphyly, not monophyly, because Nelson found Hennig s (1966) definition of monophyly adequate. Hennig s concept of monophyly seems adequately defined. I would propose to redefine the concepts of paraphyly and polyphyly with reference to a sistergroup system: Monophyly: a quality of a group including all species, or groups of species, assumed to be descendants of a hypothetical ancestral species. The members of such a group are all interrelated, for a sister-group system, and include all species of that system. Such groups may be considered complete sister-group systems. [Nelson 1971, pp. 471 472] The argument Nelson made was that Ashlock did not fully grasp Hennig s (1966) definition of monophyly. He disagreed with Ashlock s views on systematic biology, and argued for the newer Hennigian school of thought. One point that was agreed on by Nelson was that Hennig had left the terms paraphyly and polyphyly poorly defined. Definitions for these terms were constructed by Nelson on his interpretation of Hennig s meaning, namely that a paraphyletic group was one that was missing one taxon, and a polyphyletic group was one that was missing multiple taxa (Nelson 1971). Nelson s response to Ashlock seemed to be derived from Ashlock s statement that he could appease both schools of thought (i.e. evolutionary biology and cladistics) with his new definitions. His disagreement on the position of paraphyly was what spurred Nelson s dislike of Ashlock s definition. By placing paraphyly within the definition of monophyly, Ashlock (1971) had obviously changed Hennig s (1966) more specific definition of monophyly. This went against the grain of the cladists. Ashlock (1972) replied to Nelson s response, pointing out that he had no desire to accept the cladistic point of view of systematic biology. Ashlock s definitions were purely for nomenclatorial purposes, so that the proponents of both schools would be able to argue their points of view without getting confused by different definitions of the same word. Ashlock (1972) felt that cladists did not understand the meaning of paraphyletic because it had not been adequately defined by Hennig (1966). He also claimed that Hennig s (1966) definition of monophyly was ambiguous, because it did not include the common ancestor in its wording, which he felt was a source of confusion for cladists. Coupling these points of view with the fact that Ashlock agreed with all current biological classifications, it was clear Ashlock had no intention of agreeing with not only Hennig s (1966) definition of monophyly, but his theoretical position on systematic biology as well. It is unclear whether Ashlock s opinion of monophyly and cladistics was properly understood by cladists. A second response by Nelson (1973) to Ashlock stated that his concepts were inadequate because he failed to include the concept of relationships (or kinship) in his definitions, meaning that they did not fulfill the requirements of a cladistic definition. The discussion between Ashlock and Nelson was purely about defining monophyly sensu stricto. That there was both a phylogenetic and cladistic definition did not help matters, particular when these conflicted. By adopting holophyly as a new term, Ashlock (1972) had provided a partial solution. The problem of two conflicting definitions of monophyly was, and still is, an endless source of confusion for evolutionary taxonomists, phylogeneticists and cladists, with Ashlock stating the following: Finally, unless we develop a precise definition of monophyly, evolutionary and theoretical systematics will always remain more art than science. [Ashlock 1972, p. 438] Ancestors Another source of confusion, not only for the cladists, as stated by Ashlock (1972), but seemingly for the evolutionary biologists as well, was the role of the common ancestor. Ashlock believed Hennig (1966) had left out the crucial information of whether or not the common ancestor be included in a monophyletic group, which confused cladists (Ashlock 1972). However, Nelson (1973) stated that the understanding of both he and Hennig was that the common ancestor was not actually a real entity, so the inclusion of it into a monophyletic group was redundant. Nelson (1973) felt this was the basis for Hennig s phylogenetic

Defining and redefining Monophyly Australian Systematic Botany 351 systematics. However, Hennig never talked about hypothetical ancestors or of excluding ancestors from his definition of monophyly. Rather, the source for Nelson s new definition of monophyly, and his views on the artificial ancestor, may have stemmed from Brundin s (1966) definition. Hennig (1965) was actually very clear in his views, stating the following: In morphological systems, the beginner which belongs to each group is a formal idealistic standard ( Archetype ) whose connections with the other members of the group are likewise purely formal and idealistic. But, in a phylogenetic system, the beginner to which each group formation relates is a real reproductive community which has at some time in the past really existed as the ancestral species of the group in question, independently of the mind which conceives it, and which is linked by genealogical connections with the other members of the group and only with these. [Hennig 1965, p. 99, our emphasis] The debate over the definition of monophyly therefore appears to have started with Ashlock and Nelson arguing from a mixture of the definitions supplied in Hennig (1965, 1966) and Brundin (1966). Ashlock, representing the evolutionary biologists, found Hennig s views on the definition of monophyly simultaneously restrictive and ambiguous. Nelson, representing the cladists, stated that he agreed with Hennig s definition of monophyly, even though it is clear he is not actually agreeing with Hennig s stance on the common ancestor, and is probably using the first part of Brundin s definition, namely, that [A] monophyletic group (?) is every group of the system fulfilling the demand that any species belonging to it is more closely related to any other species likewise belonging to the group than to any species which does not belong to it. [Brundin 1966, p. 17] It is not surprising that Nelson would refer to Brundin rather than Hennig. Most early cladists in Europe were exposed to Hennig through Brundin s(1966) monograph, but not Ashlock, who would have read straight from Hennig (1950). Ashlock (1972) was concerned that there were two concepts being argued as the same term, namely monophyly. One concept was that the common ancestor plays a pivotal role in the definition of a monophyletic group (i.e. the time concept), as initially introduced by Bigelow (1956) and defined by Hennig (1966, first definition). The other concept was that a common ancestor is not necessary because the definition should relate only to relationships (i.e. the concept of kinship), as mentioned by Brundin (1966) in the first part of his definition, in Hennig s second definition (Hennig 1966) and Nelson (1971, 1973). Diamonophyly and synmonophyly The monophyly debate did not only result in three distinct definitions of monophyly, but also in two very distinct interpretations of a branching diagram (Fig. 1). In Fig. 1, wefind that birds are monophyletic and reptiles are aphyletic. All three sides of the debate (i.e. Ashlock, Hennig and Nelson) would identify the grouping of birds as Fig. 1. Cladogram demonstrating the monophyly of birds v. the aphyly of reptiles. monophyletic, with the exception of Ashlock, who would see both reptiles and birds as conditions of monophyly, that is, paraphyly and holophyly respectively. All parties would consider reptiles and birds together as monophyletic. Although all three parties would identify the branching structure as monophyletic or holophyletic, they would, however, define it differently. The differences in definition are based on what assumptions or inferences are made. Those that see the birds as being more closely related to one another than they are to reptiles are making a statement of classification, which is based on shared derived characters (synapomorphies). Those that make the inference that the relationship involves a most recent common ancestor, are making a claim about phylogeny, that is, synapomorphies and symplesiomorphies (see Nixon and Carpenter 2012). The most recent common ancestor and plesiomorphies are inferred from synapomorphy. The differences between the two definitions may appear to be trivial; however, they differ greatly at the level of interpretation and theory. The first and second group (i.e. Ashlock, Hennig), i.e. those that considered monophyly to be a stem group, and those that defined relationship as requiring an ancestor, or ancestral state, were making a claim about inference, namely ancestral descendant relationships. Notions of ancestry, however, require a concept of time (i.e. complete chronology or a literal unbroken ancestor descent lineage); we use the Greek prefix dia- (complete or through) to distinguish a chronological or inferential monophyly. We, therefore, propose that Ashlock s and Hennig s definitions are diamonophyletic definitions. The third group (i.e. Nelson), i.e. those that considered monophyly to be topographical relations, did not require notions of ancestry to justify claims of relationship. Rather, a monophyletic taxon is based only on evidence, and not inference. Given that such evidence identifies which two taxa are more closely related together than to a third, we use the prefix syn (together). Thus, we propose that Nelson s definition of monophyly is a synmonophyletic definition. In defining diamonophyly and synmonophyly, we can separate the two interpretations of monophyly used in the literature, namely, taxa that require some form of explanation to make a claim about relationship, and taxa that are defined on the basis of evidence alone. These definitions become vital when distinguishing monophyly within systematics.

352 Australian Systematic Botany T. A. Vanderlaan et al. Practical uses and effect of synmonophyly and diamonophyly For practical identification purposes, a taxon or group, such as the birds in Fig. 1, can be said to be monophyletic. Monophyly is an identifiable structure within a branching diagram that can be identified without a definition. Perhaps this is why there were no precise definitions given by Haeckel (1866, 1874), who clearly used the term to identify one type of branching diagram from another. The problem with monophyly begins when systematists and phylogeneticists attempt to define it in respective terms of classification and evolutionary biology. The two terms syn- and diamonophyly are practical when interpreting branching diagrams and discussing theory. Whereas two practitioners may identify a monophyletic taxon within a branching diagram, a pattern cladist, for instance, will see a cladogram, and a process cladist will see a phylogenetic tree. Given that the branching diagram has exactly the same structure and contains the same evidence (i.e. synapomorphies), two practitioners may interpret the same structure in two entirely different ways. At this point, distinguishing between these two contrasting views becomes important to avoid confusion. Whereas the term monophyly was useful in identification, synand diamonophyly are essential in discussing theory and interpretation, as the next example demonstrates. Farris (1974) and the methodological application of monophyly In 1974, Farris published updated definitions of paraphyly and polyphyly, primarily for a methodological application of the terms. The reason for this was so that systematists were able to use his definitions to discover whether or not their groups were monophyletic with respect to a given tree (cladogram), this being the chief goal of phylogenetic systematics (Farris 1974). Farris was discussing the term (dia)monophyly in reference to Hennig s (1966) first definition. The definition by Farris (1974) was proposed not only for a methodological application, but also because Farris did not agree with Nelson s (1971) interpretation of Hennig s paraphyly and polyphyly. Farris claimed that Hennig s definitions specified whether the most recent common ancestor of a group belonged to that group, and Nelson s specified membership only for known species (Farris 1974). He wanted to specify in his definitions that polyphyletic groups were defined by convergent characters, whereas paraphyletic groups were defined by plesiomorphic characters (both unobserved and inferred a posteriori to analysis). This, claimed Farris, was more in line with Hennig s (1966) original views, namely, that The group is said to be monophyletic if its group membership character appears uniquely derived and unreversed. The group is said to be paraphyletic if its group membership character appears uniquely derived, but reversed. The group is said to be polyphyletic if its group membership character appears non-uniquely derived. [Farris 1974, p. 554] The definitions, and subsequent usage of them, were strongly supported by Platnick (1977). Platnick (1977), although commending both Hennig s (1966) and Nelson s (1971) definitions of the terms paraphyly and polyphyly, was concerned about the position of monotypic genera. He claimed that Hennig s (1966) definitions were too ambiguous, because Hennig (1966) distinguished between (dia)monophyletic groups and non-(dia)monophyletic (paraphyletic and polyphyletic) groups by genealogical relationships existing within these groups, and not on the ability to recognise the relationships. This was a problem for Platnick, because he felt that Hennig was inconsistent between his theoretical definitions and his belief in their purpose. That is to say, although Hennig could define paraphyly and polyphyly, the definitions in themselves were unable to be used to discover paraphyly and polyphyly (Platnick 1977). This was the reason for Platnick (1977) supporting Farris s (1974) updated definitions of the terms paraphyly and polyphyly, and subsequently (our) diamonophyly. Farris v. Hull The publication of Hull s (1988) Science as a Process caused a brief dispute on the history of the definition of monophyly between himself and Farris (Farris 1990, 2007; Hull 1990). The dispute arose from the fact that Hull (1988) claimed that the debate (between Ashlock and the cladists ) was based on each side attributing their version to Haeckel s(1874)definition. This caused a further response from Farris (1990). Farris (1990) raised issues with Hull s book, in response to the claim that Haeckel was being used by both sides of the debate. The first point Farris chose to make focused on the mistake Hull made of attributing Nelson and Platnick to ridiculing Ashlock at a systematics conference in 1980. According to Hull (1988), Nelson and Platnick had obviously done their homework. They came primed with historical references designed to show that the term monophyly went back to Haeckel and that Haeckel had used it in Hennig s sense. They celebrated their defeat of Ashlock by raising a toast to the great Haeckel. [Hull 1988, p. 192] This was denied by Farris on behalf of Nelson and Platnick (Farris 1990), claiming it was he who spoke to Ashlock, namely, that Ashlock could hardly have been surprised in 1980 by the news of Haeckel s authorship of the term, for he had earlier (Ashlock, 1979: 441) discussed it himself. Nor did Nelson (pers. comm.) take part in such an encounter. Platnick (pers. comm.) discussed monophyly with Ashlock at that social, but not Haeckel s definition... It was I who discussed Haeckel s work with Ashlock. [Farris 1990, pp. 81 82]. Hull s defence was that he made an error in his notes, but did not believe Farris had merely discussed Haeckel s terms for a historical reference, and that rather, it was probably Farris who ridiculed Ashlock (Hull 1990). This was responded to again by Farris (2007) by calling Hull a liar, as follows: No, Hull s point in that anecdote was to cover for Ashlock and to lie about Haeckel s tree. And it wasn t another and it wasn tan error... And they were not errors at all, but

Defining and redefining Monophyly Australian Systematic Botany 353 consisted of Hull changing history to support Mayr s preposterous claims. [Farris 2007, p. 8] Probably the more plausible point made by Farris (1990) was that neither the evolutionary biologists nor the cladists originally attributed their definitions of monophyly to Haeckel. Haeckel was not mentioned in terms of definitions of monophyly by Hennig (1966), Ashlock (1971, 1972), Nelson (1971) or even by Farris himself (Farris 1974). Nor did Ashlock ever attribute his traditional definition to Haeckel in his early papers (Ashlock 1971, 1972). Simpson s definition, used by Mayr and Ashlock, did not make reference to the original author of the term (Simpson 1961; Farris 1990). The first mention of Haeckel s use of monophyly was in Mayr (1974), although it was not until 1979 when Ashlock discussed Haeckel s original meaning (Ashlock 1979, 1984). This was the fatal flaw in Hull s (1988) argument that both sides (evolutionary biologists and cladists) were using Haeckel as a sort of poster child for monophyly. Hull defended his position on the use of Haeckel in the debate about the definition because he wanted to express how scientists use historical citations to defend their work (Hull 1990). At a later point in his response, however, Hull claimed that the historical accuracy of Haeckel sdefinition of monophyly was irrelevant to the current use, stating the following: The point I attempted to make, however, is that historical accuracy is not all that important in such endeavors... Farris and I agree that Haeckel s use of the term monophyly is fundamentally irrelevant to the issue of which usage contemporary systematists should adopt. [Hull 1990, p. 398] In turn, he defended the fact that the authors did not originally use Haeckel in this way. Unfortunately, the contradiction that authors used Haeckel as a historical figure for the definition, and then the view that Haeckel s definition was irrelevant for current use of the term monophyly leant no credibility to Hull s (1988) stance. It appears that Hull (1990) realised his mistake in Hull (1988) too late, and was backtracking. Farris (2007, p. 8) claimed that Hull twisted the truth of history to support his agreement with the evolutionary biologists Mayr, Simpson and Ashlock. It certainly appears that Hull was unable to get his story straight in regard to Haeckel. The debate and Hull s (1988) claim, however, stirred up the question about Haeckel and his influence on the current definition, if there ever was any. What about Haeckel? Haeckel was the first to use the term monophyly within a figure caption (Haeckel 1866, plate I). Haeckel defined monophyly several years later, as...a monophyletic concept of the animal kingdom as a single root-form and all of its descendants. [Ashlock 1984, p. 42, translated from Haeckel 1874] Definitions of monophyly during the 1940 to the 1960s were not actually attributed to Haeckel directly. Neither Mayr s (1942) nor Bigelow s (1956) definition of monophyly, used by Hennig (1966) to create his first definition, included a citation to Haeckel. Neither did Hennig (1966). Brundin (1966) used Hennig s (1950) original definition, whereas Ashlock (1971) cited Simpson (1961), whose definition did not refer to Haeckel. Finally, Nelson (1971) and Farris (1974) cited Hennig (1966) as their main source, whereas the earliest definitions by Mayr (1942), Bigelow (1956) and Simpson (1961) were not cited. Ashlock first cited Haeckel in his 1979 paper. He stated that Haeckel (1874) originally coined the term monophyly, and that it was used by Haeckel to support Darwin s Origin of Species claim that groups of similar organisms existed because of descent from a common ancestor. This, Ashlock (1979) stated, showed that Haeckel s (1874) use of the term (dia) monophyly included paraphyletic taxa. In 1984, Ashlock argued that his use of the term (dia)monophyly was in accordance with Haeckel s (1874) definition, as meaning from a single origin. In 1990, Farris discussed Ashlock s use of Haeckel for his definition of (dia)monophyly, and stated that Ashlock did not in fact agree with Haeckel. This was because, Farris (1990) stated, Ashlock had acknowledged that Hennig s(1966)definition was in accordance with Haeckel s(1874)definition. Ashlock (1979) did state that Hennig s definition was in essence the same as Haeckel s, if, and only if, it was taken as meaning Haeckel s thoughts on the entire (dia)monophyly of life, that is that all organisms descend from one ancestor. The belief by Ashlock that his definition was more closely related to Haeckel s definition was based on Haeckel s use of paraphyletic taxa in classifications, and that it upheld the traditional views of polyphyly. The confusion between Ashlock (1979, 1984) and Farris (1990) probably stemmed from Haeckel using the term monophyly for several meanings. Uses by Haeckel for (dia) monophyly included the derivation of a species from an ancestral form, the phylogenetic differentiation of organisms forms from a primitive form, and the origin of anatomical structures, which did not have to be related to the monophyly of the taxon it was within (Rieppel 2011). In fact, Rieppel (2011) discussed in detail Haeckel s use of the term monophyly, and how its meaning cannot be determined from his publications. Given this information, it is not surprising that the redefinitions of monophyly were hindered rather than helped by the reintroduction of Haeckel in the literature. Those who consider themselves to be using Haeckel s definition are most likely to be using a diamonophyletic definition. Haeckel s numerous definitions all included a notion of genealogy, a derivation of species from an ancestor or a primitive form (see Richards 2008). Hennig also favoured a diamonophyletic definition in his later publications (Hennig 1966, 1975). However, because Haeckel did not use the term for one specific purpose, Hennig s explicit definition of (dia) monophyly has been more highly favoured, and cited, in recent literature. The diamonophyletic definition has spawned a debate on its use in population-level studies. These studies have focused on the fiercely debated species concept. Two types of monophyly are used in the literature, reciprocal monophyly in molecular systematics, and less commonly oligophyly, in population-level studies on fossils. Both refer to monophyly as a process rather than a concept.

354 Australian Systematic Botany T. A. Vanderlaan et al. A concept or a process recipriocal monophyly and oligophyly? The term reciprocal monophyly is a concept used in molecular systematics to define a group of individuals labelled as a species that are more closely related genetically to one another than to individuals labelled as other species, in regard to their maternally transmitted mitochondrial DNA (Neigel and Avise 1986; Kizirian and Donnelly 2004). The term was distinguished, by molecular systematists, from the traditional term monophyly, when it was found that mitochondrial DNAs of populations within a species were not more closely related to one another than to any other population outside of the species (Avise et al. 1983; Neigel and Avise 1986). This apparent paraphyly was explained in a phylogenetic context by Neigel and Avise, by suggesting that populations needed a certain number of generations to become monophyletic genetically. They suggested that mitochondrial DNA will transform from polyphyletic to paraphyletic to monophyletic (although sometimes polyphyly and paraphyly may not happen). By using the term monophyly in this way, they have taken a concept of relatedness and have turned it into a mechanism. Reciprocal monophyly does not in fact have much to do with the original monophyly debate, instead it has more to do with the tokogenetics v. phylogenetics debate over the inclusiveness of species. This has recently been discussed in the literature (see Nixon and Wheeler 1990; Wheeler and Meier 2000; Rieppel 2009, 2010, 2011; Assis and Rieppel 2011; Assis 2013). Like monophyly, the term reciprocal monophyly has also changed definition over time. In population genetics, reciprocal monophyly is central to the genealogical species concept. According to this concept, two groups come from different species if they form distinct monophyletic groups (Zhu et al. 2011, p. 220). In this sense, reciprocal monophyly is linked to the genealogical species concept (see De Queiroz 2007) and departs significantly from all other definitions of monophyly. Austerlitz et al. (2009) claimed that reciprocal monophyly occurs when most common recent ancestor (MRCA) of all individuals in each species is more recent than the global MRCA (p. 2), harking back to Hennig s nearest stem species. In any case, definitions for reciprocal monophyly fall squarely within the definition of diamonophyly as outlined here, because the definitions rely on the concepts of an ancestor or lineage. Similar to reciprocal monophyly, oligophyly was defined as being derived from few ancestral forms, and was defined as the opposite of monophyly in the 1960 Dictionary of Scientific Terms (Kenneth 1960). Urbanek (1998) called oligophyly near monophyly or strongly restricted polyphyly, and referred to it as a scanty ancestry. It was defined by Urbanek as...a restrictive factor in evolution leading to minimization of the number of phyletic lines owing to an occasional reduction by means of mass extinction as well as to their recovery from scanty survivors. [Urbanek 1998, p. 549] Oligophyly was used by Urbanek as a process or explanation of the concept monophyly, rather than a concept in itself, namely,...the paucity of ancestry (oligophyly) explains why both the monophyletic origin and evolutionary parallelism are such common features of the phylogeny in most fossil groups. [Urbanek 1998, p. 549] According to Urbanek, the term refers to individuals or populations that have evolved from only a few ancestors, a phenomenon existing after mass extinctions. It is used as an explanation of a process, rather than a concept, as with reciprocal monophyly. Both oligophyly and reciprocal monophyly are diamonophyletic definitions that are used at a subspecies or population level to explain the process of individuals becoming monophyletic. Conclusions The debate on the definition of monophyly has stemmed from a misconception that the term was applied in the same way methodologically and theoretically. Monophyly itself was never used by Haeckel, the original author, for one concept. Throughout the 1960s and 1970s, a debate began on what the definition should be, centring on Hennig s proposal to exclude paraphyly. In actuality, the debate stemmed from a miscommunication on the importance of the inclusion or exclusion of the common ancestor. Authors such as Hennig argued for a genealogical concept to be included in the definition, termed here as diamonophyly. Authors such as Nelson argued for a kinship concept to be included, termed here as synmonophyly. This, however, was not recognised at the time, to the confusion of other authors, in particular Ashlock, who recognised the original problem. If monophyly is split into two meanings, a debate would not be needed as to its definition, and it could be used for the appropriate situation. For example, phylogeneticists would say their group was diamonophyletic if its taxa all stemmed from one common ancestor, which includes a notion of genealogy. Systematists, however, would say their group was synmonophyletic if all taxa in question were more closely related to one another than to any outside taxa, including a notion of kinship only. References Ashlock PD (1971) Monophyly and associated terms. Systematic Zoology 20, 63 69. doi:10.2307/2412223 Ashlock PD (1972) Monophyly again. Systematic Zoology 21, 430 438. doi:10.2307/2412435 Ashlock PD (1974) The uses of cladistics. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 5, 81 99. doi:10.1146/annurev.es.05.110174.000501 Ashlock PD (1979) An evolutionary systematist s view of classification. Systematic Zoology 28, 441 450. doi:10.2307/2412559 Ashlock PD (1984) Monophyly: its meaning and importance. In Cladistics: Perspectives on the Reconstruction of Evolutionary History. (Eds T Duncan, TF Stuessy) pp. 39 46. (Columbia University Press: New York) Assis LCS (2013) Species and tokogenetic homologies: 10 sutras. Cladistics doi:10.1111/cla.12031[published online early 4 June 2013] Assis LCS, Rieppel O (2011) Are monophyly and synapomorphy the same or different? Revisiting the role of morphology in phylogenetics. Cladistics 27, 94 102. doi:10.1111/j.1096-0031.2010.00317.x Austerlitz F, David O, Schaeffer B, Bleakley K, Olteanu M, Leblois R, Veuille M, Laredo C (2009) DNA barcode analysis: a comparison of phylogenetic and statistical classification methods. BMC Bioinformatics 10, S10 doi:10.1186/1471-2105-10-s14-s10 Avise JC, Shapira JF, Daniel SW, Aquadro CF, Lansman RA (1983) Mitochondrial DNA differentiation during the speciation process in Peromyscus. Molecular Biology and Evolution 1, 38 56.

Defining and redefining Monophyly Australian Systematic Botany 355 Bigelow RS (1956) Monophyletic classification and evolution. Systematic Zoology 5, 145 146. doi:10.2307/2411915 Bock WJ (1968) Phylogenetic systematics, cladistics and evolution. Evolution 22, 646 648. doi:10.2307/2406888 Bock WJ (1973) Philosophical foundations of classical evolutionary classification. Systematic Zoology 22, 375 392. doi:10.2307/2412945 Borgmeier T (1957) Basic questions of systematics. Systematic Zoology 6, 53 69. doi:10.2307/2411802 Brundin L (1966) Transantarctic relationships and their significance, as evidenced by chironomid midges; with a monograph of the subfamilies Podonominae and Aphroteniinae and the austral Heptagyiae. Kungliga Svenska Vetenskapsakademiens Handlinger 11(1), 1 472. Cain AJ, Harrison GA (1958) An analysis of the taxonomist s judgment of affinity. Proceedings of the Zoological Society of London 1, 85 98. Colless DH (1967) The phylogenetic fallacy. Systematic Zoology 16, 289 295. doi:10.2307/2412148 Darlington PJ (1970) A practical criticism of Hennig Brundin phylogenetic systematics and antarctic biogeography. Systematic Zoology 19, 1 18. doi:10.2307/2412024 Darlington PJ (1972) What is cladism? Systematic Biology 21, 128 129. doi:10.1093/sysbio/21.1.128 De Queiroz K (2007) Species concepts and species delimitation. Systematic Biology 56, 879 886. doi:10.1080/10635150701701083 Ebach MC, Williams DM (2010) Aphyly: a systematic designation for a taxonomic problem. Evolutionary Biology 37(2-3), 123 127. doi:10.1007/s11692-010-9084-5 Farris JS (1974) Formal definitions of paraphyly and polyphyly. Systematic Zoology 23, 548 554. doi:10.2307/2412474 Farris JS (1990) Haeckel, history, and Hull. Systematic Zoology 39, 81 88. doi:10.2307/2992211 Farris JS (2007) Processed science. Darwiniana 45, 7 8. Haeckel E (1866) Generelle Morphologie der Organismen. Erster Band: allgemeine Anatomie der Organismen. (Georg Reimer: Berlin) Haeckel E (1874) The gastraea-theory, the phylogenetic classification of the animal kingdom, and the homology of the germ-lamellae. The Quarterly Journal of Microscopical Science 14, 142 165. Hennig W (1950) Grundzüge einer Theorie der phylogenetischen Systematik. (Deutscher Zentralverlag: Berlin) Hennig W (1953) Kritische Bemerkungen zum phylogenetischen System der Insekten. Beiträge Zur Entomologie 3, 1 85. Hennig W (1965) Phylogenetic systematics. Annual Review of Entomology 10, 97 116. doi:10.1146/annurev.en.10.010165.000525 Hennig W (1966) Phylogenetic Systematics. (University of Illinois Press: Urbana, IL) Hennig W (1975) Cladistic analysis or cladistic classification? A reply to Ernst Mayr. Systematic Zoology 24, 244 256. doi:10.2307/2412765 Hull DL (1988) Science as a Process. (University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL) Hull DL (1990) Farris on Haeckel, history and Hull. Systematic Zoology 39, 397 399. doi:10.2307/2992360 Kenneth JH (1960) A Dictionary of Scientific Terms. (Oliver and Boyd: Edinburgh) Kiriakoff SG (1959) Phylogenetic systematics versus topology. Systematic Zoology 8, 117 118. doi:10.2307/2411772 Kizirian D, Donnelly MA (2004) The criterion of reciprocal monophyly and classification diversity at the species level. Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution 32, 1072 1076. doi:10.1016/j.ympev.2004.05.001 Mayr E (1942) Systematics and the Origin of Species: From the Viewpoint of a Zoologist. (Columbia University Press: New York) Mayr E (1965) Numerical phenetics and taxonomic theory. Systematic Zoology 14(2), 73 97. doi:10.2307/2411730 Mayr E (1969) Principles of Systematic Zoology. (McGraw-Hill: New York) Mayr E (1974) Cladistic analysis or cladistic classification? Zeitschrift für Systematik und Evolutionsforschung 12, 94 128. doi:10.1111/j.1439-0469.1974.tb00160.x Neigel JE, Avise JC (1986) Phylogenetic relationships of mitochondrial DNA under various demographic models of speciation. In Evolutionary Processes and Theory. (Eds E Nevo, S Karlin) pp. 515 534. (Academic Press: New York) Nelson GJ (1969) The problem of historical biogeography. Systematic Biology 18, 243 246. Nelson GJ (1971) Paraphyly and polyphyly redefinitions. Systematic Zoology 20, 471 472. doi:10.2307/2412125 Nelson GJ (1972) Comments on Hennig s phylogenetic systematics and its influence on ichthyology. Systematic Zoology 21, 364 374. doi:10.2307/2412429 Nelson GJ (1973) Monophyly again? A reply to P. D. Ashlock. Systematic Zoology 22, 310 312. doi:10.2307/2412311 Nelson GJ (1994) Homology and systematics. In Homology: The Hierarchical Basis of Comparative Biology. (Ed. BK Hall) pp. 102 138 (Academic Press: San Diego, CA) Nixon KC, Carpenter JM (2012) On homology. Cladistics 28, 160 169. doi:10.1111/j.1096-0031.2011.00371.x Nixon KC, Wheeler QD (1990) An amplification of the phylogenetic species concept. Cladistics 6, 211 223. doi:10.1111/j.1096-0031.1990.tb00541.x Platnick NI (1977) Paraphyletic and polyphyletic groups. Systematic Zoology 26, 195 200. doi:10.2307/2412841 Richards R (2008) Tragic Sense of Life: Ernst Haeckel and the Struggle over Evolutionary Thought. (University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL) Richter S, Meier R (1994) The development of phylogenetic concepts in Hennig s early theoretical publications (1947 1966). Systematic Biology 43(2), 212 221. Rieppel O (2009) Hennig s enkaptic system. Cladistics 25, 311 317. doi:10.1111/j.1096-0031.2009.00260.x Rieppel O (2010) Species monophyly. Journal of Zoological Systematics and Evolutionary Research 48, 1 8. doi:10.1111/j.1439-0469.2009.00545.x Rieppel O (2011) Ernst Haeckel (1834 1919) and the monophyly of life. Journal of Zoological Systematics and Evolutionary Research 49, 1 5. doi:10.1111/j.1439-0469.2010.00580.x Sattler R (1964) Methodological problems in taxonomy. Systematic Zoology 13, 19 27. doi:10.2307/2411433 Schmitt M (2013) From taxonomy to Phylogenetics: Life and Work of Willi Hennig. (Koninklijke Brill: Leiden, the Netherlands) Simpson GG (1961) Principles of Animal Taxonomy. (Columbia University Press: New York) Slater JA, Polhemus JT (1990) Obituary: Peter D. Ashlock 1929 1989. Journal of the New York Entomological Society 98, 113 122. Sokal RR, Camin JH (1965) The two taxonomies: areas of agreement and conflict. Systematic Zoology 14, 176 195. doi:10.2307/2411548 Urbanek A (1998) Oligophyly and evolutionary parallelism: a case study of Silurian graptolites. Acta Palaeontologica Polonica 43, 549 572. Wheeler QD, Meier R (2000) Species Concepts and Phylogenetic Theory: a Debate. (Columbia University Press: New York) Zhu S, Degnan JH, Steel M (2011) Clades, clans, and reciprocal monophyly under neutral evolutionary models. Theoretical Population Biology 79, 220 227. doi:10.1016/j.tpb.2011.03.002 Zimmermann W (1931) Arbeitsweise der botanischen Phylogenetik und anderer Gruppierungswissenschaften. In Handbuch der vergleichenden Anatomie der Wirbeltiere, (Eds L Bolk, E Goppaert, E Kallius, W Lubosch), Band 9, pp. 942 1053. (Urban & Schwarzenberg: Berlin) www.publish.csiro.au/journals/asb